Let's Be Logical
Logic is something that is practiced everyday in a civilized society. When most people think about logic they most often think of axiomatic principals that allow us to live in relative harmony with the society, the universe, that humanity has created. Something wholly logical, something beneficial to all of mankind, is ensuring that trash and recycling goes into a trash bin or a proper receptacle so that our individual footprint does not negatively impact the image and cleanliness of our neighborhoods which helps ensure, as much as possible with unceasing human creation of waste, that we can maintain at least some semblance of a habitable planet for future generations of humans. If placing trash and recycling in the proper receptacle is logical then littering, not ensuring that trash and recycling is placed in the proper place of disposal is not only the activity of a misanthrope sociopath, it is categorically illogical.
Even in something as beneficial to all of humanity as taking out the trash and not leaving it all over the street to rot and fester disease and pollute the air and all of society with the foul stench of human squander, there is an exception to the rule that everyone must put their trash and recycling into the proper bins. If all the bins in the all the world are full and there is an inevitable overflow of human filth all over the streets that is not just a consequence of humanity’s rampant materialist culture, it is a logical exception to the rule. This is also an example of informal logic.
According to Canadian philosopher Leo Groarke, “informal logic is the attempt to build and to understand and improve thinking, reasoning, and argument as they occur in real life contexts: in public discussion and debate; in education and intellectual exchange; in interpersonal relations; and in law, medicine and other professions. It combines the study of argument, evidence, proof and justification with an instrumental outlook which emphasizes its usefulness in the analysis of real life arguing.” Informal logic is used by community leaders, politicians, business owners, aristocrats, educators and others who have influence over society to help govern, to help do what is best (hopefully) for the whole of society, or at least their constituents. Most would agree that in informal logic, despite the exception of a trash-burdened planet, polluted by the scourge of humanity’s inability to obtain satisfaction, littering is a trespass that society has to be against for the sustainability of our planet and the ability to continue the practice of argumentation.
Example
1:
“If everyone littered like Jonny
litters the world would become uninhabitable. Everyone in the world including
Jonny litters. Therefore the world becomes uninhabitable.”
• Argument (or reasoning or proof that
an idea is true most often governed by empiricism): If Jonny litters and all
seven billion people on the planet litter the planet will become unlivable. (We
have seen the effects of littering and pollution on the environment, especially
since industrialization)
• Conclusion (or what the argument is
trying to prove): Littering will make the world uninhabitable
• Premise (or what the argument assumes
to be true): humanity cannot live in a world filled with garbage and dross
• Inference (the connection between the
premise and the conclusion; the truth of the premise establishes the truth of
the conclusion): Humanity cannot live in a world filled with garbage so we
should not litter.
Despite the perceived logic of being
more conscious of how the environment is treated some misanthrope can argue
that death is coming to us all and that the planet will eventually die just
like of all of us, the planet has had many world ending events and maybe
humanity is supposed to drown in disgusting heaps of our own vain materialism.
Natural
language can be used, debates of informal logic can become heated shouting
matches. The arguments can be propaganda laden and only show a corrupt agenda
to poison not only the environment but also the discourse of human progress.
Informal logic is essentially critical thinking and is not bound by any true
rules of conduct, its focus is on the premise and the inference and both can be
evaluated using all manners of epistemology.'
There is a way that logic is
formalized, a manner in which you can deal with such statements that does not
involve any ambiguous banter about the benefits or negative conclusions
associated with these philosophical debates, moral imperatives; there is no
empirical data to assess, a logic that does not appraise the premise of an
argument, just the inference. Each inference is then evaluated as “True”
or “False” or “Valid” or “Invalid.” We have to first
regiment the language according to specific details that allow us to focus more
on the structure of the language rather than the existential content. Symbolic
logic, according to 19th Century Scottish mathematician, “may be
defined as the science of reasoning by the aid of representative symbols; these
symbols being employed to be synonymous substitutes for longer expressions. […]
When any expression verbal or symbolic, of inconvenient length has to be
written frequently in the course of an argument or investigation, we naturally
cast about for some short and simple symbol to represent and replace it”
(McColl, 493).
We can prove “If everyone littered like
Jonny litters the world would become uninhabitable. Jonny and the everyone else
in the world litters, therefore the world becomes uninhabitable,” is valid, by
using a highly regimented formal logical language. Rules and symbols must be
established to prove that the proposition is valid. Since I am writing in
English we will use the range of the English alphabet, capitol letters, to represent
the main clauses in the propositions.
We
use the rules of inference specifically modus ponendo
ponens or modus ponens which is Latin for “the way that affirms by affirming”
and is denoted by the formula P → Q, P |- Q.
This rule ensures that the condition
is replaced by the consequence.
Example
1.1:
Jonny
= the letter “J”
Everyone
in the world = the letter “E”
Uninhabitable
= the letter “U”
“If J and E. U. Therefore U”
So if J and E imply U and J and E are
asserted to be “True” or “Valid” then U must be true, or If J and E. U.
Therefore U. We can also simplify the expression further by using more symbols
completing the transformation to a complete logical expression formatted into
the logical formal language.
^ is used for a conjunction,
substitute for the word “and”
→ is used for conditional propositions, "if and then propositions.
⊢ is used for provability; Provability logic is a modal logic that is used to investigate what arithmetical theories can express in a restricted language about their provability predicates.
⊢ is used for provability; Provability logic is a modal logic that is used to investigate what arithmetical theories can express in a restricted language about their provability predicates.
Now we can complete the logical expression using the formal
logical language:
J^E→U, J^E ⊢U
The statement still holds true in the new logical language,
but to ensure the truth of the proposition a proof must be offered.
1. J^E → U
P
2. J^E P
2. J^E P
3. U 1, 2 MP
The
proof works out so this is a valid argument.
There is another form called modus tollens which is Latin for “the way that denies by denying.” It is another rule of inference that makes a valid argument by denying the consequent of a particular proposition.
We
use the symbol “~” for the word not or for negation.
Example
2:
“If Jonny is in his apartment then he
will answer the door. Jonny does not answer the door. Therefore he is not at
home.”
J → D, ~D ⊢ ~J
Proof:
If Jonny is in his apartment then he
will answer the door. Jonny does not answer the door. Therefore he is not at
home.”
J → D, ~D ⊢ ~J
1. J → D
P
2. ~D P
3. ~J 1, 2 MT
This
argument is valid.
Using this argumentation we can prove
that the misanthrope may not be so wrong about their indifference about a trash
filled planet.
Example 2.1:
Example 2.1:
“If everyone littered like Jonny
litters the world would become uninhabitable. Esther wants to live in an
uninhabitable world. Jonny and everyone litters therefore Esther is happy.”
Esther
= S
J^E → U, J^E, S → U ⊢ U
1. J^E → U P
2. J^E P
2. J^E P
3. S → U P
4. S 1, 2 MP
5. U 3, 4 MP
This argument is valid.
Who knows how Esther will survive in a world consumed by all of our humanly dander but she is going to try and be delighted in doing so. The application of the formal language of logic hopefully is not being used for such devious planning or argumentation as the want for our world to be swallowed by human filth but that is how you formalize logic. It limits the abstraction of ideas so that we do not lose time and focus on debate about the principalities involved in every detail of existence.
There are still arguments that are
truly invalid based upon the premise and structure of the proposition that the
symbols just cannot follow. The following are classic example of using invalid
reference forms and how we can prove the invalidity of an argument. There are
two inference forms, the fallacy of assuming the consequent and the fallacy of
negating the antecedent.
Here
is an example of a fallacy assuming the consequent:
Example 3:
“If the course isn’t easy then we’ll
need to study. We don’t need to study. If the course requires very little
reading then it’s easy. Therefore the course requires very little reading.”
~E → S, ~S, L → E |- L
1. ~E → S P
2. ~S P
3. L → E P
4. E 1, 2 MT
5. L 3, 4 FAC
Example 3.1:
“If he’s the best candidate then he’ll
get the job. He’s the best candidate. If he doesn’t get the job then he won’t
be happy. Therefore he’ll be happy.”
B → J, B, ~J → ~H |- H
1. B → J P
2. B P
3. ~J → ~H P
4. J 1, 2 MP
5. H 3, 4 FNA
That is how logic becomes a formal
language. It removes all the ambiguity and all of the ancillary concepts and
big ideas that could get us caught up in this long, drawn out, Aristotelian
philosophical debates about proper etiquette and decorum and what is in the
best interest of humankind or us individually. Formal logic or symbolic logic
lets us with the near certainty of mathematics find a basis in argumentative
structure that can help us to understand at least the modes that can help us
argue better, which can help us make better decisions, which can help humanity
not succumb to a planet plagued by our excess.
Sources:
- Verbrugge, Rineke (L.C.), "Provability Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/logic-provability/
- McColl, Hugh. Mind, Volume VI, Issue 4, 1 January 1897, Pages 493–510, https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/VI.4.493.01 January 1897
- Groarke, Leo, "Informal Logic", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.)
- https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/List_of_logic_symbols
- http://philosophy.lander.edu/logic/symbolic.html
- https://www4.uwsp.edu/philosophy/dwarren/WhatIsFormalLogic/WhatIsFormalLogicSlides.pdf
Comments
Post a Comment